ENERGY AND EQUITY
Ivan Illich, copyright 1974
Printed in Great Britain by Ebenezer Baylis and Son
Limited
The Trinity Press, Worcester, and London
Ivan Illich, CIDOC, Apdo. 479, Cuernavaca, Mor.,
Mexico
The Energy
Crisis
It has recently
become fashionable to insist on an impending energy crisis. This euphemistic
term conceals a contradiction and consecrates an illusion. It masks the
contradiction implicit in the joint pursuit of equity and industrial growth. It
safeguards the illusion that machine power can indefinitely take the place of
manpower. To face this contradiction and betray this illusion, it is urgent to
clarify the reality that the language of crisis obscures: high quanta of energy
degrade social relations just as inevitably as they destroy the physical
milieu.
The proponents of
an energy crisis confirm and continue to propagate a peculiar vision of man.
According to this notion, man is born into prolonged dependence on slaves which
he must painfully learn to master. If he does not employ prisoners, then he
needs motors to do most of his work. According to this doctrine, the well-being
of a society can be measured by the number of years its members have gone to
school and by the number of energy slaves they have thereby learned to command.
This belief is common to the conflicting economic ideologies now in vogue. It
is threatened by the obvious inequity, harriedness and impotence that appear
everywhere once the voracious hordes of energy slaves outnumber people by a
certain proportion. The energy crisis focuses concern on the scarcity of fodder
for these slaves. I prefer to ask whether free men need them.
The energy
policies adopted during the current decade will determine the range of social
relationships a society will be able to enjoy by the year 2000. A low energy
policy allows for a wide choice of life styles and cultures. If, on the other
hand, a society opts for high energy consumption, its social relations must be
dictated by technocracy and will be equally distasteful whether labelled
capitalist or socialist.
At this moment,
most societies -- especially the poor ones -- are still free to set their
energy policies by any of three guidelines. Well-being can be identified with
high amounts of per capita energy use, with high efficiency of energy
transformation, or with the least possible use of mechanical energy by the most
powerful member of society. The first approach would stress tight management of
scarce and destructive fuels on behalf of industry, whereas the second would
emphasise the retooling of industry in the interest of thermodynamic thrift.
Both attitudes necessarily imply huge public expenditures and increased social
control; both rationalise the emergence of a computerised Leviathon, and both
are at present widely discussed.
The possibility of
a third option is barely noticed. While people have begun to accept ecological
limits on maximum per capita energy use as a condition for physical survival,
they do not yet think about the use of minimum feasible power as the foundation
of any of various social orders that would be both modern and desirable. Yet
only a ceiling on energy use can lead to social relations that are characterised
by high levels of equity. The one option that is presently neglected is the
only choice within the reach of all nations. It is also the only strategy by
which a political process can be used to set limits on the power of even the
most motorised bureaucrat. Participatory democracy postulates low energy
technology. Only participatory democracy creates the conditions for rational
technology.
What is generally
overlooked is that equity and energy can grow concurrently only to a point.
Below a threshold of per capita wattage, motors improve the conditions for
social progress. Above this threshold, energy grows at the expense of equity.
Further energy affluence then means decreased distribution of control over that
energy.
The widespread
belief that clean and abundant energy is the panacea for social ills is due to
a political fallacy, according to which equity and energy consumption can be
indefinitely correlated, at least under some ideal political conditions.
Labouring under this illusion, we tend to discount any social limit on the
growth of energy consumption. But if ecologists are right to assert that
non-metabolic power pollutes, it is in fact just as inevitable that, beyond a
certain threshold, mechanical power corrupts. The threshold of social disintegration
by high-energy quanta is independent from the threshold at which energy
conversion produces physical destruction. Expressed in horsepower, it is
undoubtedly lower. This is the fact which must be theoretically recognised
before a political issue can be made of the per capita wattage to which a
society will limit its members.
Even if
non-polluting power were feasible and abundant, the use of energy on a massive
scale acts on society like a drug that is physically harmless but psychically
enslaving. A community can choose between Methadone and 'cold turkey' --
between maintaining its addiction to alien energy and kicking it in painful
cramps -- but no society can have a population that is at once autonomously
active and hooked on progressively larger numbers of energy slaves.
In previous
discussions, I have shown that, beyond a certain level of GNP, the cost of
social control must rise faster than total output and become the major
institutional activity within an economy. Therapy administered by educators,
psychiatrists and social workers must converge with the designs of planners,
managers and salesmen, and complement the services of security agencies, the
military and the police. I now want to indicate one reason why increased
affluence requires increased control over personnel. I argue that beyond a
certain median per capita energy level, the political system and cultural
context of any society must decay. Once the critical quantum of per capita
energy is surpassed, education for the abstract goals of a bureaucracy must
supplant the legal guarantees of personal and concrete initiative. This quantum
is the limit of social order.
I will argue here
that technocracy must prevail as soon as the ratio of mechanical power and
metabolic energy oversteps a definite, identifiable threshold. The order of
magnitude within which this threshold lies is largely independent from the
level of technology applied, yet its very existence has slipped into the
blindspot of social imagination in both rich and medium rich countries. Both
the United States and Mexico have passed the critical divide. In both
countries, further energy inputs increase inequality, inefficiency and personal
impotence. Although one country has a per capita income of $500 and the other
of nearly $5,000, huge vested interest in an industrial infrastructure prods
both of them to further escalate the use of energy. As a result, both North
American and Mexican ideologues put the label of 'energy crisis' on their
frustration, and both countries are blinded to the fact that the threat of
social breakdown is due neither to a shortage of fuel, nor to the wasteful,
polluting and irrational use of available wattage, but to the attempt of
industries to gorge society with energy quanta that inevitably degrade, deprive
and frustrate most people.
A people can be
just as dangerously overpowered by the wattage of its tools as by the caloric
content of its foods, but it is much harder to confess to a national
overindulgence in wattage than to a sickening diet. The per capita wattage that
is critical for social well-being lies within an order of magnitude which is
far above the horsepower known to four-fifths of humanity and far below the
power commanded by any Volkswagen driver. It eludes the underconsumer and the
overconsumer alike. Neither is willing to face the facts. For the primitive,
the elimination of slavery and drudgery depends on the introduction of
appropriate modern technology, and for the rich, the avoidance of an even more
horrible degradation depends on the effective recognition of a threshold in
energy consumption beyond which technical processes begin to dictate social
relations. Calories are both biologically and socially healthy only as long as
they stay within the narrow range that separates enough from too much.
The so-called
energy crisis is, then, a politically ambiguous issue. Public interest in the
quantity of power and in the distribution of controls over the use of energy
can lead in two opposite directions. On the one hand, questions can be posed
that would open the way to political reconstruction by unblocking the search
for a post-industrial, labour-intensive, low energy and high equity economy. On
the other hand, hysterical concern with machine fodder can reinforce the
present escalation of capital-intensive institutional growth, and carry us past
the last turnoff from a hyper-industrial Armageddon. Political reconstruction
presupposes the recognition of the fact that there exist critical per capita
quanta beyond which energy can no longer be controlled by political
process. Social breakdown will be the inevitable outcome of ecological
restraints on total energy use imposed by industrially minded planners
bent on keeping industrial production at some hypothetical maximum.
Rich countries
like the United States, Japan or France might never reach the point of choking
in their own waste, but only because their societies will have already
collapsed into a socio-cultural energy coma. Countries like India, Burma and,
for another short while at least, China, are in the inverse position of being
still muscle-powered enough to stop short of an energy stroke. They could
choose, right now, to stay within those limits to which the rich will be forced
back at an enormous loss in their vested interest.
The choice of a
minimum energy economy compels the poor to abandon distant expectations and the
rich to recognise their vested interest as a ghastly liability. Both must
reject the fatal image of man the slaveholder currently promoted by an
ideologically stimulated hunger for more energy. In countries that were made
affluent by industrial development, the energy crisis serves as a whip to raise
the taxes which will be needed to substitute new, more sober and socially more
deadly industrial processes for those that have been rendered obsolete by
inefficient overexpansion. For the leaders of people who have been disowned by
the same process of industrialisation, the energy crisis serves as an alibi to
centralise production, pollution and its control in a last-ditch effort to
catch up with the more highly powered. By exporting their crisis and by
preaching the new gospel of Puritan energy worship, the rich do even more
damage to the poor than they did by selling them the products of now outdated
factories. As soon as a poor country accepts the doctrine that more energy more
carefully managed will always yield more goods for more people, that country is
hooked into the race for enslavement to maximum industrial outputs. Inevitably
the poor abandon the option for rational technology when they choose to
modernise their poverty by increasing their dependence on energy. Inevitably
the poor reject the possibility of liberating technology and participatory
politics when, together with maximum feasible energy use, they accept maximum feasible
social control.
The energy crisis
cannot be overwhelmed by more energy inputs. It can only be dissolved, along
with the illusion that well-being depends on the number of energy slaves a man
has at his command. For this purpose, it is necessary to identify the
thresholds beyond which power corrupts, and to do so by a political process
that associates the community in the search for limits. Because this kind of
research runs counter to that now done by experts and for institutions, I shall
call it counterfoil research. It has three steps. First, the need for limits on
the per capita use of energy must be theoretically recognised as a social
imperative. Then, the range must be located wherein the critical magnitude
might be found. Finally, each community has to identify the levels of inequity,
harrying and operant conditioning that its members are willing to accept in
exchange for the satisfaction that comes of idolising powerful devices and
joining in rituals directed by the professionals who control their operation.
The need for
political research on socially optimal energy quanta can be clearly and
concisely illustrated by an examination of modern traffic. The United States
puts 45 per cent of its total energy into vehicles: to make them, run them and
clear a right of way for them when they roll, when they fly and when they park.
Most of this energy is to move people who have been strapped into place. For
the sole purpose of transporting people, 250 million Americans allocate more
fuel than is used by 1,300 million Chinese and Indians for all purposes. Almost
all this fuel is burnt in a rain dance of time-consuming acceleration. Poor
countries spend less energy per person, but the percentage of total energy
devoted to traffic in Mexico or in Peru is greater than in the USA, and it
benefits a smaller percentage of the population. The size of this enterprise
makes it both easy and significant to demonstrate the existence of socially
critical energy quanta by the example of personal carriage.
In traffic, energy
used over a specific period of time (power) translates into speed. In this
case, the critical quantum will appear as a speed limit. Wherever this limit
has been passed, the basic pattern of social degradation by high-energy quanta
has emerged. Once some public utility went faster than 15 mph, equity declined
and the scarcity of both time and space increased. Motorised transportation
monopolised traffic and blocked self-powered transit. In every Western country,
passenger mileage on all types of conveyance increased by a factor of a hundred
within fifty years of building the first railroad. When the ratio of their
respective power outputs passed beyond a certain value, mechanical transformers
of mineral fuels excluded people from the use of their metabolic energy and
forced them to become captive consumers of conveyance. This effect of speed on
the autonomy of people is only marginally affected by the technological
characteristics of the motorised vehicles employed or by the persons or
entities who hold the legal titles to airlines, buses, railroads or cars. High
speed is the critical factor which makes transportation socially destructive. A
true choice among political systems and of desirable social relations is
possible only where speed is restrained. Participatory democracy demands low
energy technology, and free people must travel the road to productive social
relations at the speed of a bicycle.*
* I speak about
traffic for the purpose of illustrating the more general point of socially
optimal energy use, and I restrict myself to the locomotion of persons,
including their personal baggage and the fuel, materials and equipment used for
the vehicle and the road. I purposely abstain from the discussion of two other
types of traffic: merchandise and messages. A parallel argument can be made for
both, but this would require a different line of reasoning, and I leave it for
another occasion.
The
Industrialisation of Traffic
The discussion of
how energy is used to move people requires a formal distinction between
transport and transit as the two components of traffic. By traffic I
mean any movement of people from one place to another when they are outside of
their homes. By transit I mean those movements that put human metabolic
energy to use, and by transport that mode of movement which relies on
other sources of energy. These energy sources will henceforth be mostly motors,
since animals compete fiercely with men for their food in an overpopulated
world, unless they are thistle eaters like donkeys and camels.
As soon as people
become tributaries of transport, not only when they travel for several days,
but also on their daily trips, the contradictions between social justice and
motorised power, between effective movement and higher speed, between personal
freedom and engineered routing, become poignantly clear. Enforced dependence on
auto-mobile machines then denies a community of self-propelled people just
those values supposedly procured by improved transportation.
People move well
on their feet. This primitive means of getting around will, on closer analysis,
appear quite effective when compared with the lot of people in modern cities or
on industrialised farms. It will appear particularly attractive once it has
been understood that modern Americans walk, on the average, as many miles as
their ancestors -- most of them through tunnels, corridors, parking lots and
stores.
People on their
feet are more or less equal. People solely dependent on their feet move on the
spur of the moment, at three to four miles per hour, in any direction and to
any place from which they are not legally or physically barred. An improvement
on this native degree of mobility by new transport technology should be
expected to safeguard these values and to add some new ones, such as greater
range, time economies, comfort, or more opportunities for the disabled. So far
this is not what has happened. Instead, the growth of the transportation
industry has everywhere had the reverse effects. From the moment its machines
could put more than a certain horsepower behind any one passenger, this
industry has reduced equality among men, restricted their mobility to a system
of industrially defined routes and created time scarcity of unprecedented
severity. As the speed of their vehicles crosses a threshold, citizens become
transportation consumers on the daily loop that brings them back to their home,
a circuit which the United States Department of Commerce calls a 'trip' as
opposed to the 'travel' for which Americans leave home equipped with a
toothbrush.
More energy fed
into the transportation system means that more people move faster over a
greater range in the course of every day. Everybody's daily radius expands at
the expense of being able to drop in on an acquaintance or walk through the
park on the way to work. Extremes of privilege are created at the cost of
universal enslavement. An elite packs unlimited distance into a lifetime of
pampered travel, while the majority spend a bigger slice of their existence on
unwanted trips. The few mount their magic carpets to travel between distant
points that their ephemeral presence renders both scarce and seductive, while
the many are compelled to trip further and faster and to spend more time
preparing for and recovering from their trips.
In the United
States, four-fifths of all man-hours on the road are those of commuters and
shoppers who hardly ever get into a plane, while four-fifths of the mileage
flown to conventions and resorts is covered year after year by the same one and
a half per cent of the population, usually those who are either well-to-do or
professionally trained to do good. The speedier the vehicle, the larger the
subsidy it gets from regressive taxation. Barely 0.2 per cent of the entire US
population can engage in self-chosen air travel more than once a year, a few
other countries can support a jet set which is that large.
The captive
tripper and the reckless traveller become equally dependent on transport.
Neither can do without it. Occasional spurts to Acapulco or to a Party Congress
dupe the ordinary passenger into believing that he has made it into the shrunk
world of the powerfully rushed. The occasional chance to spend a few hours
strapped into a high-powered seat makes him an accomplice in the distortion of
human space, and prompts him to consent to the design of his country's
geography around vehicles rather than around people. Man has evolved physically
and culturally together with his cosmic niche. What for animals is their
environment he has learned to make into his home. His self-image requires as
its complement a life-space and a life-time integrated by the pace at which he
moves. If that relationship is determined by the velocity of vehicles rather
than by the movement of people, man the architect is reduced to the status of a
mere commuter.
The typical
American male devotes more than 1,600 hours a year to his car. He sits in it
while it goes and while it stands idling. He parks it and searches for it. He
earns the money to put down on it and to meet the monthly instalments. He works
to pay for petrol, tolls, insurance, taxes and tickets. He spends four of his
sixteen waking hours on the road or gathering his resources for it. And this
figure does not take into account the time consumed by other activities
dictated by transport: time spent in hospitals, traffic courts and garages;
time spent watching automobile commercials or attending consumer education
meetings to improve the quality of the next buy. The model American puts in
1,600 hours to get 7,500 miles: less than five miles per hour. In countries
deprived of a transportation industry, people manage to do the same, walking
wherever they want to go, and they allocate only three to eight per cent of
their society's time budget to traffic instead of 28 per cent. What
distinguishes the traffic in rich countries from the traffic in poor countries
is not more mileage per hour of life-time for the majority, but more hours of
compulsory consumption of high doses of energy, packaged and unequally
distributed by the transportation industry.
Speed-Stunned
Imagination
Past a certain
threshold of energy consumption, the transportation industry dictates the
configuration of social space. Motorways expand, driving wedges between
neighbours and removing fields beyond the distance a farmer can walk.
Ambulances take clinics beyond the few miles a sick child can be carried. The
doctor will no longer come to the house, because vehicles have made the
hospital the right place to be sick. Once heavy lorries reach a village high in
the Andes, part of the local market disappears. Later, when the high school
arrives at the plaza along with the paved highway, more and more of the young
people move to the city, until not one family is left which does not long for a
reunion with someone hundreds of miles away, down on the coast.
Equal speeds have
equally distorting effects on the perception of space, time and personal
potency in rich and in poor countries, however different the surface
appearances might be. Everywhere, the transportation industry shapes a new kind
of man to fit the new geography and the new schedules of its making. The major
difference between Guatemala and Kansas is that in Central America some people
are still exempt from all contact with vehicles and are, therefore, still not
degraded by their dependence on them.
The product of the
transportation industry is the habitual passenger. He has been boosted out of
the world in which people still move on their own, and he has lost the sense
that he stands at the centre of his world. The habitual passenger is conscious
of the exasperating time scarcity that results from daily recourse to the cars,
trains, buses, undergrounds and lifts that force him to cover an average of
twenty miles each day, frequently crossing his path within a radius of less
than five miles. He has been lifted off his feet. No matter if he goes by
underground or jetplane he feels slower and poorer than someone else and
resents the shortcuts taken by the privileged few who can escape the
frustrations of traffic. If he is cramped by the timetable of his commuter
train, he dreams of a car. If he is exhausted by the rush hour, he envies the
speed capitalist who drives against the traffic. If he must pay for his car out
of his own pocket, he knows full well that the commanders of corporate fleets
send the fuel bill to the company and write off the rented car as a business
expense. The habitual passenger is caught at the wrong end of growing inequality,
time scarcity and personal impotence, but he can see no way out of this bind
except to demand more of the same: more traffic by transport. He stands in wait
of technical changes in the design of vehicles, roads and schedules; or else he
expects a revolution to produce mass rapid transport under public control. In
neither case does he calculate the price of being hauled into a better future.
He forgets that he is the one who will pay the bill, either in fares or in
taxes. He overlooks the hidden costs of replacing private cars with equally
rapid public transport.
The habitual
passenger cannot grasp the folly of traffic based overwhelmingly on transport.
His inherited perceptions of space and time and of personal pace have been
industrially deformed. He has lost the power to conceive of himself outside of
the passenger role. Addicted to being carried along, he has lost control over
the physical, social and psychic powers that reside in man’s feet. The
passenger has come to identify territory with the untouchable landscape through
which he is rushed. He has become impotent to establish his domain, mark it
with his imprint and assert his sovereignty over it. He has lost confidence in
his power to admit others into his presence and to share space consciously with
them. He can no longer face the remote by himself. Left on his own, he feels
immobile.
The habitual
passenger must adopt a new set of beliefs and expectations if he is to feel
secure in the strange world where both liaisons and loneliness are products of conveyance.
To ‘gather’ for him means to be brought together by vehicles. He comes to
believe that political power grows out of the capacity of a transportation
system, and in its absence is the result of access to the television screen. He
takes freedom of movement to be the same as one’s claim on propulsion. He
believes that the level of democratic process correlates to the power of
transportation and communications systems. He has lost faith in the political
power of the feet and of the tongue. As a result, what he wants is not more
liberty as a citizen but better service as a client. He does not insist on his
freedom to move and to speak to people but on his claim to be shipped and to be
informed by media. He wants a better product rather than freedom from servitude
to it. It is vital that he come to see that the acceleration he demands is
self-defeating, and that it must result in a further decline of equity, leisure
and autonomy.
Net Transfer of
Lifetime
Unchecked speed is
expensive and progressively fewer can afford it. Each increment in the velocity
of a vehicle results in an increase in the cost of propulsion,
track-construction and – most dramatically – in the space the vehicle devours
while it is on the move. Past a certain threshold of energy consumption for the
fastest passenger, a worldwide class structure of speed capitalists is created.
The exchange value of time becomes dominant, and this is reflected in language:
time is spent, saved, invested, wasted and employed. As societies put price tags
on time, equity and vehicular speed correlate inversely.
High speed
capitalises a few people’s time at an enormous rate but, paradoxically, it does
this at a high cost in time for all. In Bombay, only a very few people own
cars. They can reach a provincial capital in one morning and make the trip once
a week. Two generations ago, this would have been a week-long trek once a year.
They now spend more time on more trips. But these same few also disrupt, with
their cars, the traffic flow of thousands of bicycles and pedicabs that move
through downtown Bombay at a rate of effective locomotion superior to that of
downtown Paris, London or New York. The compounded, transport-related time
expenditure within a society grows much faster than the time economies made by
a few people on their speedy excursions. Traffic grows indefinitely with the
availability of transports. Beyond a critical threshold, the output of the
industrial complex established to move people costs a society more time than it
saves. The marginal utility of an increment in the speed of a small number of
people has for its price the growing marginal disutility of this acceleration
for the great majority.
Beyond a critical
speed, no one can save time without forcing another to lose it. The man who claims
a seat in a faster vehicle insists that his time is worth more than that of the
passenger in a slower one. Beyond a certain velocity, passengers become
consumers of other people’s time, and accelerating vehicles become the means
for effecting a net transfer of life-time. The degree of transfer is measured
in quanta of speed. This time-grab despoils those who are left behind, and
since they are the majority, it raises ethical issues of a more general nature
than kidney dialysis or organ transplants.
Beyond a certain
speed, motorised vehicles create remoteness which they alone can shrink. They
create distances for all and shrink them for only a few. A new dirt road
through the wilderness brings the city within view, but not within reach, of
most Brazilian subsistence farmers. The new expressway expands Chicago, but it
sucks those who are well-wheeled away from a downtown that decays into a
ghetto.
Man’s speed
remained unchanged from the Age of Cyrus to the Age of Steam. News could not
travel more than a hundred miles per day, no matter how the message was
carried. Neither the Inca’s runners nor the Venetian galley, the Persian
horseman or the mail coach under Louis XIV, could break the barrier. Soldiers,
explorers, merchants and pilgrims moved at twenty miles per day. In
Valéry’s words, Napoleon still had to move at Caesar’s slowness: Napoleon
va à la même lenteur que César. The Emperor knew that
‘public prosperity is measured by the income of the coaches’: On
mésure la prospérité publique aux comptes des diligences,
but he could barely speed them up. Paris-Toulouse had required about 200 hours
in Roman times, and the scheduled stagecoach still took 158 hours in 1782. Only
the nineteenth century accelerated man. By 1830, the trip had been reduced to
110 hours, but at a new cost. In the same year, 4,150 stagecoaches overturned
in France, causing more than a thousand deaths. Then the railroad brought a sudden
change. By 1855, Napoleon III claimed to have travelled an average of 96
kilometres per hour on the train between Paris and Marseille. Within one
generation, the average distance travelled each year per Frenchman increased
one hundred and thirty times, and Britain’s railroad network reached its
greatest expansion. Passenger trains attained their optimum cost calculated in
terms of time spent for their maintenance and use.
With further
acceleration, transportation began to dominate traffic, and speed began to
erect a hierarchy of destinations. By now, each set of destinations corresponds
to a specific level of speed and defines a certain passenger class. Each
circuit of terminal points degrades those pegged at a lower number of miles per
hour. Those who must get around on their own power have been redefined as
underdeveloped outsiders. Tell me how fast you go and I’ll tell you who you
are. If you can corner the taxes which fuel the Concorde, you are certainly at
the top.
Over the last two
generations, the vehicle has become the sign of career achievement, just as the
school has become the sign of starting advantage. At each new level, the
concentration of power must produce its own kind of rationale. So, for example,
the reason that is usually given for spending public money to make a man travel
more miles in less time each year is the still greater investment that was made
to keep him more years in school. His putative value as a capital-intensive
production tool sets the rate at which he is being shipped. Other ideological
labels besides ‘a good education’ are just as useful for opening the cabin door
to luxuries paid for by others. If the Thought of Chairman Mao must now be
rushed around China by jet, this can only mean that two classes are needed to
fuel what his revolution has become, one of them living in the geography of the
masses and the other in the geography of the cadres. The suppression of
intermediary levels of speed in Popular China has certainly made the
concentration of power more efficient and rational, but it also underscores the
new difference in value between the time of the bullock driver and the time of
the jet-driven. Accelerating speed inevitably concentrates horsepower under the
seats of a few and compounds the increasing time-lack of most commuters with
the further sense that they are lagging behind.
The need for
unequal privilege in an industrial society is generally advocated by means of
an argument with two sides. The hypocrisy of this argument is clearly betrayed
by acceleration. Privilege is accepted as the necessary pre-condition to
improve the lot of a growing total population, or it is advertised as the
instrument for raising the standards of a deprived minority. In the long run,
accelerating transportation does neither. It only creates a universal demand
for motorised conveyance, and puts previously unimaginable distances between
the various layers of privilege. Beyond a certain point, more energy means less
equity.
The
Ineffectiveness of Acceleration
It should not be
overlooked that top speeds for a few exact a different price than high speeds
for all. Social classification by levels of speed enforces a net transfer of
power: the poor work and pay to get left behind. But if the middle classes of a
speed society may be tempted to ignore discrimination, they should not neglect
the rising marginal disutilities of transportation and their own loss of
leisure. High speeds for all mean that everybody has less time for himself as
the whole society spends a growing slice of its time budget on moving people.
Vehicles running over the critical speed not only tend to impose inequality,
they also inevitably establish a self-serving industry that hides an
inefficient system of locomotion under apparent technological sophistication. I
will argue that a speed limit is necessary not only to safeguard equity; it is
equally a condition for increasing the total distance travelled within a
society, while decreasing the total time that travel takes.
There is little
research available on the impact of vehicles on the twenty-four-hour time
budget of individuals and societies. From transportation studies, we get
statistics on the cost of time per mile, on the value of time measured in
dollars or in length of trips. But these statistics tell us nothing about the
hidden costs of transportation: about how traffic nibbles away at life-time,
about how vehicles devour space, about the multiplication of trips made
necessary by the existence of vehicles, or about the time spent directly and
indirectly preparing for locomotion. Further, there is no available measure of
the even more deeply buried costs of transport, such as higher rent to live in
areas convenient to the flow of traffic, or the cost of protecting these areas
from the noise, pollution and danger to life and limb that vehicles create. The
lack of an account of expenditures from the social time budget should not lead
us to believe, however, that such an accounting is impossible, nor should it
prevent our drawing conclusions from the little that we do know.
From our limited
information it appears that everywhere in the world, after some vehicle broke
the barrier of 15 mph, time scarcity related to traffic began to grow. After
industry had reached this threshold of per capita output, transport made of man
a new kind of waif: a being constantly absent from a destination he cannot
reach on his own but must reach within the day. By now, people work a
substantial part of every day to earn the money without which they could not
even get to work. The time a society spends on transportation grows in
proportion to the speed of its fastest public conveyance. Japan now leads the
United States in both areas. Life-time gets cluttered up with activities
generated by traffic as soon as vehicles crash through the barrier that guards
people from dislocation and space from distortion.
Whether the
vehicle that speeds along the public freeway is owned by the state or by an
individual has little to do with the time scarcity and overprogramming that
rise with every increment in speed. Buses use one-third of the fuel which cars
burn to carry one man over a given distance. Commuter trains are up to ten
times more efficient than cars. Both could become even more efficient and less
polluting. If publicly owned and rationally managed, they could be so scheduled
and routed that the privileges they presently provide under private ownership
and incompetent organisation would be considerably cut. But as long as any
system of vehicles imposes itself on the public by its unlimited top speed, the
public is left to choose between spending more time to pay for more people to
be carried from station to station, and paying less taxes so that even fewer
people can travel in much less time much further than others. The order of
magnitude of the top speed which is permitted within a transportation system
determines the slice of its time budget than an entire society spends on
traffic.
A desirable
ceiling on the velocity of movement cannot be usefully discussed without
returning to the distinction between self-powered transit and motorised transport,
and comparing the contribution each component makes relative to the total
locomotion of people, which I have called traffic.
Transport stands
for the capital-intensive mode of traffic and transit indicates the
labour-intensive mode. Transport is the product of an industry whose clients
are passengers. It is an industrial commodity and therefore scarce by
definition. Improvement of transport always takes place under conditions of
scarcity that become more severe as the speed – and with it the cost – of the
service increases. Conflict about insufficient transport tends to take the form
of a zero-sum game where one wins only if another loses. At best, such a
conflict allows for the solution of the Prisoner’s Dilemma: by cooperating with
their jailer, both prisoners get off with less time in the cell.
Transit is not the
product of an industry, but the independent enterprise of transients. It has
use value by definition but need not have any exchange value. The ability to
engage in transit is native to man and more or less equally distributed among
healthy people of the same age. The exercise of this ability can be restricted
by depriving some class of people of the right to take a straight route, or
because a population lacks shoes or pavements. Conflict about unsatisfactory
transit conditions tends to take, therefore, the form of a non-zero-sum game in
which everyone comes out ahead – not only the people who get the right to walk
through a formerly walled property, but also the owner who now gets a road.
Total traffic is
the result of two profoundly distinct modes of production. These can reinforce
each other harmoniously only as long as the autonomous outputs are protected
against the encroachment of the industrial product.
The harm done by
contemporary traffic is due to the monopoly of transport. The allure of speed
has deceived the passenger into accepting the promises made by an industry that
produces capital-intensive traffic. He is convinced that high-speed vehicles
have allowed him to progress beyond the limited autonomy he enjoyed when moving
under his own power. He has allowed planned transport to predominate over the
alternative of labour-intensive transit. Destruction of the physical
environment is the least noxious effect of this concession. The far more bitter
results are the multiplication of psychic frustration, the growing disutilities
of continued production, and subjection to an inequitable transfer of power –
all of which are manifestations of a distorted relationship between life-time
and life-space. The passenger who agrees to live in a world monopolised by
transport becomes a harassed, overburdened consumer of distances whose shape
and length he can no longer control.
Every society that
imposes compulsory speed submerges transit to the profit of transport. Wherever
not only privilege but also elementary necessities are denied to those who do
not use high-speed conveyances, an involuntary acceleration of personal rhythms
is imposed. Industry dominates traffic as soon as daily life comes to depend on
motorised trips.
This profound
control of the transportation industry over natural mobility constitutes a
monopoly much more pervasive than either the commercial monopoly Ford might win
over the automobile market, or the political monopoly car manufacturers might
wield against the development of trains and buses. Because of its hidden,
entrenched and structuring nature, I call this a radical monopoly. Any
industry exercises this kind of deep-seated monopoly when it becomes the
dominant means of satisfying needs that formerly occasioned a personal
response. The compulsory consumption of a high-powered commodity (motorised
transport) restricts the conditions for enjoying an abundant use value (the
innate capacity for transit). Traffic serves here as the paradigm of a general
economic law: Any industrial product that comes in per capita quanta beyond
a given intensity exercises a radical monopoly over the satisfaction of a need.
Beyond some point, compulsory schooling destroys the environment for learning,
medical delivery systems dry up the non-therapeutic sources of health, and
transportation smothers traffic.
Radical monopoly
is first established by a rearrangement of society for the benefit of those who
have access to the larger quanta, then it is enforced by compelling all to
consume the minimum quantum in which the output is currently produced.
Compulsory consumption will take on a different appearance in industrial branches
where information dominates, such as education or medicine, than it will in
those branches where quanta can be measured in British thermal units, such as
housing, clothing or transport. The industrial packaging of values will reach
critical intensity at different points with different products but, for each
major class of outputs, the threshold occurs within an order of magnitude that
is theoretically identifiable. The fact that it is possible theoretically to
determine the range of speed within which transportation develops a radical
monopoly over traffic does not mean that is possible theoretically to determine
just how much of such as monopoly any given society will tolerate. The fact
that it is possible to identify a level of compulsory instruction at which
learning by seeing and doing declines does not enable the theorist to identify
the specific pedagogical limits to the division of labour that a culture will
tolerate. Only recourse to juridical and, above all, to political process can
lead to the specific, though provisional, measures by which speed or compulsory
education will actually be limited in a given society. The magnitude of
voluntary limits is a matter of politics; the encroachment of radical monopoly
can be pinpointed by social analysis.
A branch of
industry does not impose a radical monopoly on a whole society by the simple
fact that it produces scarce products, or because it drives competing
industries off the market, but rather by virtue of its acquired ability to
create and shape the need which it alone can satisfy.
Shoes are scarce
all over Latin America and many people never wear them. They walk on the bare
soles of their feet, or wear the world’s widest variety of excellent sandals,
supplied by a range of artisans. Their transit is in no way restricted by their
lack of shoes. But in some countries of South America people are compelled to
be shod ever since access to schools, jobs and public services was denied to
the barefoot. Teachers or party officials define the lack of shoes as a sign of
indifference toward ‘progress’. Without any intentional conspiracy between the
promoters of national development and the shoe industry, the barefoot in these
countries are now barred from any office.
Schools, like
shoes, were scarce at all times. But it was never the small number of
privileged pupils that turned the school into an obstacle for learning. Only
when laws were enacted to make schools both compulsory and free did the
educator assume the power to deny learning opportunities on the job to the
underconsumer of educational therapies. Only when school attendance had become
obligatory did it become feasible to impose on all a progressively more complex
artificial environment into which the unschooled and unprogrammed do not fit.
The potential of a
radical monopoly is unmistakeable in the case of traffic. Imagine what would
happen if the transportation industry could somehow distribute its output more
adequately: a traffic Utopia of free rapid transportation for all would
inevitably lead to a further expansion of traffic’s domain over human life.
What would such a Utopia look like? Traffic would be organised exclusively
around public transportation systems. It would be financed by a progressive tax
calculated on income and on the proximity of one’s residence to the next
terminal and to the job. It would be designed so that everybody could occupy
any seat on a first-come, first-served basis: the doctor, the vacationer and
the President would not be assigned any priority of person. In this fool’s paradise,
all passengers would be equal, but they would be just as equally captive
consumers of transport. Each citizen of a motorised Utopia would be deprived of
the use of his feet and drafted into the servitude of proliferating networks of
transportation.
Certain would-be
miracle makers disguised as architects offer a specious escape from the paradox
of speed. By their standards, acceleration imposes inequities, time loss and
controlled schedules only because people do not yet live in those patterns and
orbits into which vehicles can best place them. These futuristic architects
would house and occupy people in self-sufficient units of towers interconnected
by tracks for high-speed capsules. Soleri, Doxiadis or Fuller would solve the
problem created by high-speed transport by identifying the entire human habitat
with the problem. Rather than asking how the earth’s surface can be preserved
for people, they ask how reservations for necessary people can be established
on an earth that has been reshaped for the sake of industrial outputs.
The Elusive
Threshold
Any
traffic-optimal speed for transport seems capricious or fanatical to the
confirmed passenger, whereas it looks like the flight of the bird to the donkey
driver. Four or six times the speed of a man on foot constitutes a threshold
too low to be deemed worthy of consideration by the habitual passenger and too
high to convey the sense of a limit to the three-quarters of
humanity who still get around on their own power.
All those who plan
other people’s housing, transportation or education belong to the passenger
class. Their claim to power is derived from the value their employers place on
acceleration. Social scientists can build a computer model of traffic in
Calcutta or Santiago, and engineers can design monorail webs according to
abstract notions of traffic flow. Since these planners are true believers in
problem solving by industry, the real solution for traffic congestion is beyond
their grasp. Their belief in the effectiveness of power blinds them to the
disproportionately greater effectiveness of abstaining from its use. Traffic
engineers have yet to combine in one simulation model the mobility of people
with that of vehicles. The engineer cannot conceive the possibility of
renouncing speed and slowing down for the sake of permitting optimal traffic
flow. He would never entertain the thought of programming his computer on the
stipulation that no motorised vehicle in any city should ever overtake the
speed of a velocipede. The development expert who looks down compassionately
from his Land Rover on the Indian peasant driving his pigs to market refuses to
acknowledge the relative advantage of feet. The expert tends to forget that
this man has dispensed ten others in his village from spending time on the
road, whereas the engineer and every member of his family separately devote a
major part of every day to being in traffic. For a man who believes that human
mobility must be conceived in terms of indefinite progress, there can be no
optimal level of traffic but only passing consensus on a given level of
technical development.
Most Mexicans, not
to speak of Indians and Chinese, are in a position inverse to that of the
confirmed passenger. The critical threshold is entirely beyond what all but a
few of them know or expect. They still belong to the class of the self-powered.
Some of them have a lingering memory of a motorised adventure, but most of them
have no personal experience of travelling at or above the critical speed. In
the two typical Mexican states of Guerrero and Chiapas, less than one per cent
of the population moved even once over ten miles in less than one hour during
1970. The vehicles into which people in these areas are sometimes crowded
render traffic indeed more convenient, but barely faster than the speed of a
bicycle. The third class bus does not separate the farmer from his pig, and it
takes them both to market without inflicting any loss of weight, but this
acquaintance with motorised ‘comfort’ does not amount to dependence on
destructive speed.
The order of
magnitude in which the critical threshold of speed can be found is too low to
be taken seriously by the passenger, and too high to concern the peasant. It is
so obvious it cannot be easily seen. The proposal of a limit to speed within
this order of magnitude engenders stubborn opposition. It exposes the addiction
of industrialised men to consuming ever higher doses of energy, while it asks
those who are still sober to abstain from something they have yet to taste.
To propose
counterfoil research is not only a scandal, it is also a threat. Simplicity
threatens the expert, who supposedly understands just why the commuter train
runs at 8:15 and 8:41 and why it must be better to use fuel with certain
additives. That a political process could identify a natural magnitude, both
inescapable and limited, is an idea that lies outside the passenger’s world of
verities. He has let respect for specialists he doesn’t even know turn into
unthinking submission. If a political resolution could be found for problems
created by experts in the field of traffic, then perhaps the same remedy could
be applied to problems of education, medicine or urbanisation. If the order of
magnitude of traffic optimal vehicular velocities could be determined by laymen
actively participating in an ongoing political process, then the foundation on
which the framework of every industrial society is built would be shattered. To
propose such research is politically subversive. It puts in question the
overarching consensus on the need for more transportation which now allows the
proponents of public ownership to define themselves as political adversaries of
the proponents of private enterprise.
Degrees of
Self-Powered Mobility
A century ago, the
ball-bearing was invented. It reduced the coefficient of friction by a factor
of a thousand. By applying a well-calibrated ball-bearing between two neolithic
millstones, a man could now grind in a day what took his ancestors a week. The
ball-bearing also made possible the bicycle, allowing the wheel – probably the
last of the great neolithic inventions – finally to become useful for
self-powered mobility.
Man, unaided by
any tool, gets around quite efficiently. He carries one gram of his weight over
a kilometre in ten minutes by expending 0.75 calories. Man on his feet is
thermodynamically more efficient than any motorised vehicle and most animals.
For his weight, he performs more work in locomotion than rats or oxen, less
than horses or sturgeon. At this rate of efficiency man settled the world and
made its history. At this rate peasant societies spend less than five per cent
and nomads less than eight per cent of their respective social time budgets
outside the home or the encampment.
Man on a bicycle
can go three or four times faster than the pedestrian, but uses five times less
energy in the process. He carries one gram of his weight over a kilometre of
flat road at an expense of only 0.15 calories. The bicycle is the perfect
transducer to match man’s metabolic energy to the impedance of locomotion.
Equipped with this tool, man outstrips the efficiency of not only all machines,
but all other animals as well.
The invention of
the ball-bearing, the tangent-spoked wheel and the pneumatic tyre taken
together can be compared to only three other events in the history of
transportation. The invention of the wheel at the dawn of civilisation took the
load off man’s back and put it onto the barrow. The invention and simultaneous
application, during the European Middle Ages, of stirrup, shoulder harness and
horseshoe increased the thermodynamic efficiency of the horse by a factor of up
to five, and changed the economy of medieval Europe: it made frequent ploughing
possible and thus introduced rotation agriculture; it brought more distant
fields into the reach of the peasant, and thus permitted landowners to move
from six-family hamlets into 100-family villages, where they could live around
the church, the square, the jail and – later – the school; it allowed the
cultivation of northern soils and shifted the centre of power into cold
climates. The building of the first ocean-going vessels by the Portuguese in
the fifteenth century, under the aegis of developing European capitalism, laid
the solid foundations for a globe-spanning culture and market.
The invention of
the ball-bearing signalled a fourth revolution. It created an option between
more freedom in equity and more speed. The bearing is an equally fundamental
ingredient of two new types of locomotion, respectively symbolised by the
bicycle and the car. The bicycle lifted man’s automobility into a new order,
beyond which progress is theoretically not possible. In contrast, the
accelerating individual capsule enabled societies to engage in a ritual of
progressively paralysing speed.
The monopoly of a
ritual application over a potentially useful device is nothing new. Thousands
of years ago, the wheel took the load off the carrier-slave, but it did so only
on the Eurasian landmass. In Mexico, the wheel was well-known, but never
applied to transport. It served exclusively for the construction of carriages
for toy gods. The taboo on wheelbarrows in America before Cortés is no
more puzzling than the taboo on bicycles in modern traffic.
It is by no means
necessary that the invention of the ball-bearing continue to serve the increase
of energy use, and thereby produce time scarcity, space consumption and class
privilege. If the new order of self-powered mobility offered by the bicycle
were protected against devaluation, paralysis and risk to the limbs of the
rider, it would be possible to guarantee optimal shared mobility to all people
and put an end to the imposition of maximum privilege and exploitation. It
would be possible to control the patterns of urbanisation if the organisation
of space were constrained by the power man has to move through it.
Bicycles are not
only thermodynamically efficient, they are also cheap. With his much lower
salary, the Chinese acquires his durable bicycle in a fraction of the working
hours an American devotes to the purchase of his obsolescent car. The cost of
public utilities needed to facilitate bicycle traffic versus the price of an
infrastructure tailored to high speeds is proportionately even less than the
price differential of the vehicles used in the two systems. In the bicycle
system, engineered roads are necessary only at certain points of dense traffic,
and people who live far from the surfaced path are not thereby automatically
isolated as they would be if they depended on cars or trains. The bicycle has
extended man’s radius without shunting him onto roads he cannot walk. Where he
cannot ride his bike he can usually push it.
The bicycle also
uses little space. Eighteen bikes can be parked in the place of one car, thirty
of them can move along in the space devoured by a single automobile. It takes
two lanes of a given size to move 40,000 people across a bridge in one hour by
using modern trains, four to move them on buses, 12 to move them in their cars,
and only one lane for them to pedal across on bicycles. Of all these vehicles,
only the bicycle really allows people to go from door to door without walking.
The cyclist can reach new destinations of his choice without his tool creating
new locations from which he is barred.
Bicycles let
people move with greater speed without taking up significant amounts of scarce
space, energy or time. They can spend fewer hours on each mile and still travel
more miles in a year. They can get the benefit of technological breakthroughs
without putting undue claims on the schedules, energy or space of others. They
become masters of their own movements without blocking those of their fellows.
Their new tool creates only those demands which it can also satisfy. Every
increase in motorised speed creates new demands on space and time. The use of
the bicycle is self-limiting. It allows people to create a new relationship
between their life-space and their life-time, between their territory and the
pulse of their being, without destroying their inherited balance. The
advantages of modern self-powered traffic are obvious, and ignored. That better
traffic runs faster is asserted, but never proved. Before they ask people to
pay for it, those who propose acceleration should try to display the evidence
for their claim.
A grizzly contest
between bicycles and motors has just come to an end. In Vietnam, a
hyperindustrialised army tried to conquer, but could not overcome, a people
organised around bicycle speed. The lesson should be clear. High-energy armies
can annihilate people -–both those they defend and those against whom they are
launched, but they are of very limited use to a people which defends itself. It
remains to be seen if the Vietnamese will apply what they learned in war to an
economy of peace, if they will be willing to protect the values that made their
victory possible. The dismal likelihood is that the victors, for the sake of
industrial progress and increased energy consumption, will tend to defeat
themselves by destroying that structure of equity, rationality and autonomy
into which American bombers had forced them by depriving them of fuels, motors
and roads.
Dominant Versus
Subsidiary Motors
Men are born
almost equally mobile. Their natural ability speaks for the personal liberty of
each one to go wherever he or she wants to go. Citizens of a society founded on
the notion of equity will demand the protection of this right against any
abridgement. It should be irrelevant to them by what means the exercise of
personal mobility is denied, whether by imprisonment, bondage to an estate,
revocation of passport, or enclosure within an environment that encroaches on a
person’s native ability to move in order to make him a consumer of transport.
This inalienable right of free movement does not lapse just because most of our
contemporaries have strapped themselves into ideological seatbelts. Man’s
natural capacity for transit emerges as the only yardstick by which to measure
the contribution transport can make to traffic: there is only so much transport
that traffic can bear. It remains to be outlined how we can distinguish those
forms of transport that cripple the power to move from those that enhance it.
Transportation can
abridge traffic in two ways: by breaking its flow, by creating isolated sets of
destinations, and by increasing the loss of time due to traffic. I have already
argued that the key to the relation between transport and traffic is the speed
of vehicles. I have described how, past a certain threshold of speed, transport
has gone on to obstruct traffic in these three ways. It blocks mobility by
cluttering up the environment with vehicles and roads. It transforms geography
into a pyramid of circuits sealed off from one another according to levels of
acceleration. It expropriates life-time at the behest of speed.
If beyond a
certain threshold transport obstructs speed, motorised vehicles can complement
or improve traffic by permitting people to do things they could not do on foot
or on bicycle. Motors can be used to transport the sick, the lame, the old and
the just plain lazy. Motorpulleys can lift people over hills, but they can do
so peacefully only if they do not push the climber off the path. Trains can
extend the range of travel, but only if they give people equal opportunity to
come closer to each other. A well-developed transportation system running at
top speeds of 25 mph would have allowed Fix to chase Phileas Fogg around the
world in less than half of 80 days. The time engaged in travel must be, as much
as possible, the traveller’s own: only insofar as motorised transport remains
limited to speeds which leave it subsidiary to autonomous transit can a
traffic-optimal transportation system be developed.
A limit on the
power and therefore on the speed of motors does not by itself insure those who
are weaker against exploitation by the rich and powerful, who can still devise
means to live and work at better located addresses, travel with retinue in
plush carriages, and reserve a special lane for doctors and members of the
central committee. But at a sufficiently limited maximum speed, this is an
unfairness which can be reduced or even corrected by a combination of taxes and
technological devices. At unlimited top speed neither public ownership of the
means of transportation nor technical improvements in their control can ever
eliminate growing and unequal exploitation. A transportation industry is the
key to optimal production of traffic, but only if it does not exercise its
radical monopoly over personal productivity.
Underequipment,
Overdevelopment and Mature Technology
The combination of
transportation and transit that constitutes traffic has provided us with an
example of socially optimal per capita wattage and of the need for politically
chosen limits on it. Traffic is also a model for the convergence of worldwide
development goals, and a criterion by which to distinguish those countries
which are lamely underequipped from those that are destructively
overindustrialised.
A country can be
classified as underequipped if it cannot outfit each citizen with a bicycle or
provide a five-speed transmission for anyone who wants to pedal others around.
It is underequipped if it cannot provide good roads for the cycle, or free
public motorised transportation for those who want to travel for more than a
few hours in succession. No technical, economic or ecological reason exists why
such backwardness should be tolerated anywhere in 1975. It would be a scandal
if the natural mobility of a people were forced to stagnate on a pre-bicycle
level against its will.
A country can be
classified as overindustrialised when its social life is dominated by the
transportation industry, which has come to determine its class privileges, to
accentuate its time scarcity, and to tie its people more tightly to the tracks
it has laid out for them.
Beyond
underequipment and overindustrialisation, there is a place for the world of
post-industrial effectiveness, where the industrial mode of production
complements other autonomous forms of production. There is a place, in other
words, for a world of technological maturity. In terms of traffic, it is the
world of those who have tripled the extent of their daily horizon by lifting themselves
onto their bicycles. It is just as much the world marked by a variety of
subsidiary motors available for the occasions when a bicycle is not enough and
when an extra push will limit neither equity nor freedom. And it is, too, the
world of the long voyage: a world where every place is open to every person, at
his own pleasure and speed, without haste or fear, by means of vehicles that
cross distances without breaking with the earth which man walked for hundreds
of thousands of years on his own two feet.
Underequipment
keeps people enslaved to primordial nature and limits their freedom.
Overindustrialisation does not admit of differences in production and political
style. It imposes its technical characteristics on social relations. The world
of technological maturity permits a variety of political choices and cultures.
The variety diminishes, of course, as a community allows industry to grow at
the cost of autonomous production. Reasoning alone can offer no precise measure
for the level of post-industrial effectiveness and technological maturity
appropriate to a concrete society. It can only indicate in dimensional terms
the range into which these technological characteristics must fit. It must be
left to a historical community engaged in its own political process to decide
when programming, space distortion, time scarcity and inequality cease to be
worth its while. Reasoning can identify speed as the critical factor in
traffic. It cannot set politically feasible limits.
Only when top
speeds on personal carriage reflect the enlightened self-interest of a
political community can they become operative. This interest cannot be
expressed in a society where one class monopolises not only transportation, but
communication, medicine, education and weapons as well. It does not matter if
this power is held by legal owners or by entrenched managers of an industry
that is legally owned by the workers. This power must be reappropriated and
submitted to the sound judgement of the common man. The reconquest of power starts
with the recognition that expert knowledge blinds the secretive bureaucrat to
the obvious way of dissolving the energy crisis, just as it has blinded him to
recognise the obvious solution to the war in Vietnam.
There are two
roads from where we are to technological maturity: one is the road of
liberation from affluence; the other is the road of liberation from dependence.
Both roads have the same destination: the social restructuring of space that
offers to each person the constantly renewed experience that the centre of the
world is where he stands, walks and lives.
Liberation from
affluence begins on the traffic islands where the rich run into one another.
The well-sped are tossed from one island to the next and are offered but the
company of fellow passengers en route to somewhere else. The solitude of plenty
breaks down as the traffic islands gradually expand and people begin to recover
their native power to move around the place where they live. Thus, the
impoverished environment of the traffic island can embody the beginnings of
social reconstruction, and the people who now call themselves rich will break
with bondage to overefficient transport on the day they come to treasure the
horizon of their traffic islands, now fully grown, and to dread frequent
shipments from their homes.
Liberation from
dependence starts at the other end. It breaks the constriction of village and
valley and leaves behind the boredom of narrow horizons and the stifling
oppression of a world closed in on itself. To expand life beyond the radius of
tradition without scattering it to the winds of acceleration is a goal that any
poor country could achieve within a few years, but it is a goal that will be
reached only by those who reject the offer of unchecked industrial development
made in the name of an ideology of indefinite energy consumption.
Liberation from
the radical monopoly of industry is possible only where people engage in a
political process founded on the protection of optimal traffic. This
protection, in turn, demands a recognition of those energy quanta upon whose
neglect industrial society has been built. These energy quanta can carry those
who consume that much, but no more, into a post-industrial age that is
technologically mature.
Liberation which
comes cheap to the poor will cost the rich dear, but they will pay its price
once the acceleration of their transportation systems grinds traffic to a halt.
A concrete analysis of traffic betrays the truth underlying the energy crisis:
the impact of industrially packaged quanta of energy on the social environment
tends to be degrading, exhausting and enslaving, and these effects come into
play even before those which threaten the pollution of the physical environment
and the extinction of the race. The crucial point at which these effects can be
reversed is not, however, a matter of deduction, but of decision.